Transcendental Ideas: Definitions
An Overview of American Transcendentalism
Martin Bickman, University of Colorado, Boulder
Although Transcendentalism as a historical movement was limited in time from
the mid 1830s to the late 1840s and in space to eastern Massachusetts, its ripples
continue to spread through American culture. Beginning as a quarrel within the
Unitarian church, Transcendentalisms questioning of established cultural
forms, its urge to reintegrate spirit and matter, its desire to turn ideas into
concrete action developed a momentum of its own, spreading from the spheres
of religion and education to literature, philosophy, and social reform. While
Transcendentalisms ambivalence about any communal effort that would compromise
individual integrity prevented it from creating lasting institutions, it helped
set the terms for being an intellectual in America.
It is easier to note its pervasive influence, though, than it is to clarify
its doctrines. The fluidity and elusiveness of Transcendentalism was registered
even by some of its most intelligent contemporaries. Nathaniel Hawthorne, for
example, writes: He is German by birth, and is called Giant Transcendentalist,
but as to his form, his features,his substance, and his nature generally, it
is the chief peculiarity of this huge miscreant that neither he for himself
nor anybody for him has ever been able to describe them. As we rushed by the
caverns mouth we caught a hasty glimpse of him, looking somewhat like
an ill-proportioned figure but considerably more like a heap of fog and duskiness.
He shouted after us, but in so strange a phraseology that we knew not what he
meant, nor whether to be encouraged or affrighted. On an American visit,
Charles Dickens was told that whatever was unintelligible would certainly
be transcendental and Edgar Allan Poe instructs a young author to write
the Tone Transcendental by using small words but turning them upside down. A
Baltimore clergyman noted that a new philosophy has risen, maintaining
that nothing is everything in general, and everything is nothing in particular.
While these quotations imply that Transcendentalism had a language problem compounded
of foreign borrowings and oracular jargon, the underlying difficulty in comprehension
is that it was both a cause and a result of a major paradigm shift in epistemology,
in conceptualizing how the mind knows the world, the divine, and itself. Ralph
Waldo Emerson, its leading exponent, described both this shift and the derivation
of the movements name thus: It is well known to most of my audience,
that the Idealism of the present day acquired the name of Transcendental, from
the use of that term by Immanuel Kant, of Konigsberg, who replied to the skeptical
philosophy of Locke, which insisted that there was nothing in the intellect
which was not previously in the experience of the senses, by showing that there
was a very important class of ideas, or imperative forms, which did not come
by experience, but through which experience was acquired; that these were intuitions
of the mind itself; and he denominated them Transcendental forms. Transcendentalism,
then, is not as much concerned with a metaphysics that transcends our daily
lives but rather with a new view of the mind that replaces Lockes empiricist,
materialistic, and passive model with one emphasizing the role of the mind itself
in actively shaping experience. Against Lockes claim that there is nothing
in the mind not first put there through the senses, the Transcendentalists answer
with Leibnitz, yes, nothing except the mind itself. But while Kant emphasized
the power of the mind he also stressed its limits, its inability to know reality
absolutely. The Transcendentalist vision went beyond Kant in insisting that
the mind can apprehend absolute spiritual truths directly without having to
go through the detour of the senses, without the dictates of past authorities
and institutions, and without the plodding labor of ratiocination. In this sense
particularly, it was the logical-or supralogical-extension of both the Protestant
reformation and American democratic individualism.
To grasp the significance of this paradigm shift, we have to understand how
dominant, even hegemonic, Lockean thought was in America, and particularly at
Harvard College through the 1830s, where most of the male Transcendentalists
were educated. For example Edward Everett, who exemplified, along with William
Ellery Channing and Andrews Norton, the venerated group of Unitarian ministers
and public men who taught the generation of transcendentalists, impressed his
Harvard peers as a student by reciting verbatim throughout several class periods
Lockes Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Here matter melded with method,
since the chief instructional medium at Harvard and throughout American education
was the recitation, where knowledge was demonstrated by replicating
the words of the lesson without necessarily showing any operational mastery.
The Unitarians used Locke both negatively, to undermine the orthodox Calvinist
belief in original sin-if the mind is a blank slate at birth it cannot be innately
depraved-and positively, to underwrite belief in the special dispensation of
Christianity through the evidence of Jesuss miracles, sensory testimony
of his spiritual power, the flesh testifying to the word.
So while Unitarianism was more optimistic and rationalistic than the orthodoxy
it reformed, it weakened the foundation of Protestant faith by giving more authority
to what happens outside the individual conscience than within it and elevating
matter over spirit in shaping the mind. The Transcendentalists, in turn, took
advantage of the multiple meanings of idealism as both an epistemology
and as a moral and social critique of the materialism underlying
the Unitarian alliance of commercial and religious interests, an alliance called
by Emerson in another generalizing pun the Establishment, stressing
its static nature, contrasted with the Transcendentalist Movement,
a word suggesting youth, flux, and novelty.
An early challenge to the Unitarian synthesis came from a Swedenborgian, Sampson
Reed, who in a Harvard M.A. speech in 1821 and a pamphlet, Observations on the
Growth of the Mind (1826), posited a more organic unfolding of the minds
powers, at once romantic and apocalyptic: There is a unison of spirit
and nature. The genius of the mind will descend, and unite with the genius of
the rivers, the lakes, and the woods. Ironically an even stronger challenge
was from a Calvinist, James Marsh, who in 1829 published an American edition
of Coleridges Aids to Reflection, the very title of which emphasizes not
only a new epistemological doctrine but an entirely different approach to spiritual
knowledge, a turning inward to our own mental drama as the bedrock of religious
truth. Marsh, who tried to enact this vision educationally as president of the
University of Vermont, added his own Preliminary Essay, underscoring
the distinction between the understanding, that distinctly Lockean
faculty of rationalizing from the senses and the Reason, those higher
intuitions valued not only by German idealists but by mystics through the ages.
Soon afterward, Henry Hedge, a Unitarian minister equally conversant with German
thought, wrote for that denominations journal, The Christian Examiner,
a laudatory article on Coleridge that Emerson declared a living leaping
Logos. Hedge, later to be one of the first members of the informal Transcendentalist
Club that began in 1836 and met most frequently on his visits to Boston from
his Maine congregation, soon faded from the forefront of the movement through
his own caution about changing the structure of the church. He later described
himself as ecclesiastically conservative, though intellectually radical.
The issues were soon taken up by more activist Unitarian ministers such as Orestes
Brownson, who was influenced as much by French writers like Victor Cousin and
Benjamin Constant as by English and German ones. In an 1834 Christian Examiner
article, Brownson made a crucial link between the new epistemology and the limiting
temporality and instrumentality of all cultural forms, including those of religion:
Every positive form, however satisfactory it may be for the present, contains
a germ of opposition to future progress. It contracts, by the very effect of
its duration, a stationary character, that refuses to follow the intellect in
its discoveries, and the soul in its emotions. Two years later George
Ripley and Henry Furness would specifically question the Unitarian stress on
Christs miracles as opposed to more personally inward and universally
moral validations of Christianity. Emerson stated this position most eloquently
in his Divinity School Address of 1838: But the word Miracle,
as pronounced by Christian churches, gives a false impression; it is Monster.
It is not one with the blowing clover and the falling rain. Andrews Norton
soon labeled the Transcendentalist position the Latest Form of Infidelity.
Heeding his own words that there is no doctrine of the Reason which will
bear to be taught by the Understanding, Emerson refused to become entangled
in the ensuing theological debates led on the Transcendentalist front first
by Ripley and then by Theodore Parker. While these two ministers had youthful
energy and wide learning on their side, they soon found themselves embattled
and isolated within the institution as pulpit exchanges were refused and social
pressures mounted.
The controversy within the church was paralleled by another conflict between
the Establishment and the Movement in the field of education. Bronson Alcott,
one of the few non-ministerial Transcendentalists and a self-taught teacher
who had run other innovative schools in his native rural Connecticut, opened
in 1834 near the Boston Common his Temple School. Alcott translated Transcendentalism
into pedagogy by having the students shape and share their own thoughts in discussions
and journals, instead of rote memory and textbook recitation. Language was seen
as not simply a skill but the bridge between the individual soul and the physical
and social worlds, so that lessons on vocabulary and grammar were integrated
with spiritual matters.
Elizabeth Peabody, Alcotts usually unpaid assistant, brought the school
to the attention of the larger public in her 1835 Record of a School, but the
stormclouds did not break until Alcott published under his own name in 1836-37
two volumes of her transcriptions of his Conversations with Children on the
Gospels. Although the explicit outcry was against Alcotts discussions
with young children of physical birth-Andrews Norton, again in the forefront
of reaction, called it one-third absurd, one-third blasphemous, and one-third
obscene-the underlying challenge was to the very structures of church
and secular authority. By granting a Neoplatonic/Wordsworthian spiritual wisdom
to the young, Alcotts practice threatened to invert the normal flow of
teaching from adult to child, clergy to laity, institution to individual. Again,
a reversion to a more primitive and protestant Christianity was seen as subversively
to established Christianity. Despite Emersons defense in the newspapers,
Alcotts student body dwindled and he was never to be a classroom teacher
again. He did go on to pioneer, along with Margaret Fuller and Peabody herself,
that uniquely Transcendentalist form of adult education, the Conversation, where
the interplay of the participants minds becomes more important than any
specific doctrine, process more important than product. Through means like these
and Elizabeth Peabodys founding of the Kindergarten movement in postbellum
America, Transcendentalist education went underground only become a constant
progressive current in American education.
The Transcendentalists, then, lost their immediate skirmishes within the Unitarian
church and the field of education, however much their ideas were later to shape
both these institutions. An alternative strategy was to extrapolate Transcendentalist
ideas in a world outside these spheres, and no one did this more expansively
than Margaret Fuller. She applied the notions of self-reliance and equality
to gender roles in the first significant feminist essay in America, published
in 1844 in The Dial, the Transcendentalist journal she edited and helped found
in 1840. Later, the piece was expanded to the book Woman in the Nineteenth Century
(1845). She then left New England scene completely to become first literary
reviewer and then reporter on social issues for the New York Tribune, finally
widening her circle even beyond America to become involved in the failed Italian
revolution of 1848 and dying soon thereafter in a tragic shipwreck.
The largest organized secession, though, from Boston Unitarianism and its values
was the communitarian experiment in rural living known as Brook Farm, initiated
by George Ripley in 1841. The goal was to unite the mind with the hand, and
eliminate the corresponding invidious distinctions between classes in society.
Everyone participated in farm work and its excellent school on the premises
underlined the pedagogical nature of the entire enterprise. There was a tension,
however, between Trancendentalisms spontaneous anti-formalism and the
prescriptive systematic dictates of the French utopian thinker Fourier which
were increasingly taken as blueprints. Even before a disastrous and uninsured
fire the communitys vision thus became blurred, and ended in 1847. Despite
its demise and that of the even smaller, shorter-lived Fruitlands community
of Bronson Alcott, the notion of a pastoral retreat of simplicity and cooperation
confronting by example the capitalist industrialism of the larger society became
fixed in the American imagination.
Brook Farm threw into relief a basic tension in Transcendentalism between joint
action and individual development. At one pole, Emerson and Thoreau, who both
declined to be Brook Farmers, felt that improvement must begin with the self,
that many of the specific reforms rampant in Jacksonian America such as prohibition
and vegetarianism were too narrowly conceived and that to engage in social and
political action was to dissipate creative energies. One the other side were
Brownson, Peabody, and, intermittently Alcott, who felt that rampant individualism
was part of the problem, not part of the solution, and that social change could
be effected only through social means. But even Emerson and Thoreau recognized
that when evils such as slavery and imperialistic war reach a certain enormity,
one must speak out and act, and they, along with other Transcendentalists, most
notably Theodore Parker, joined the abolitionist cause.
Well before the firebell of the Civil War, Transcendentalism as a living force
seemed to be extinguished as quickly as it flared up. As Perry Miller pointed
out: Parker killed himself with overwork, and Thoreau expended himself;
Emerson dissolved into aphasia, Ripley subsided into disillusion, Hedge became
a Harvard professor. . . Brownson became a Catholic, as did Sophia Ripley, and
Elizabeth Peabody became a character. There were a number
of younger and secondary figures such as Franklin Sanborn and Thomas Wentworth
Higginson who perpetuated the movement through their memoirs and their own actions-Sanborn
ran a progressive school in Concord, Higginson encouraged women such as Emily
Dickinson to write--but the energy was gone and the social forms-clubs, periodicals
like The Western Literary Messenger and The Dial, schools and communes--had
in proper Transcendentalist fashion self-destructed.
What did remain as a living movement was the ongoing effect of Transcendentalism
in literature and philosophy. Most of the Transcendentalists were writers: they
wrote voluminous personal journals, sermons, letters, manifestoes, poems, translations,
and essays. Of this, perhaps only Emersons essays and Thoreaus Walden
were in the highest artist rank, but taken together the body of writings imply
a theory of language. As often the most influential formulations are in the
works of Emerson. In that epitome of Transcendentalism, Nature (1836), Emerson
posits language as originating in names for natural objects which, through the
doctrine of correspondences, have intrinsic spiritual and symbolic significance.
Thus, every word was once a poem, or, more specifically, a metaphor, since it
combines a sensory meaning with a more intangible or psychological one, the
natural fact conveying a corresponding spiritual fact.
But the sensory component of language begins to fade through use, as language
entropically drifts towards abstraction, and becomes only a set of one dimensional
verbal counters that buffers us from immediate perception of the inner and outer
worlds. The truly creative writer is one who can pierce this rotten diction
and fasten words again to visible things, liberating us from the most
pervasive and imprisoning of cultural forms, the categories of ordinary language.
Emerson thus rescues the creative writer from the belletristic margins of American
society to the epistemological center where the husks of old meanings are discarded
and new ones made.
This aesthetic of deconstructing conventional language to open the doors of
perception, of using fresh concrete description that at the same time has symbolic
resonance, was internalized by writers who reject any trace of Transcendentalist
metaphysics like Ernest Hemingway and William Carlos Williams (No ideas
but in things). It particularly shaped American poetry, especially when
joined with Emersons rejection of traditional poetic forms in favor of
each utterance creating its own appropriate form, a metre-making-argument.
. . a thought so passionate and alive, that, like the spirit of a plant or an
animal, it has an architecture of its own. While Emerson himself and the
younger poets he directly nurtured like Jones Very, a mad Harvard tutor, and
Ellery Channing, the neer do well nephew of William Ellery Channing, formulator
of American Unitarianism, were unable to make a successfully break from regular
forms, Walt Whitman and Emily Dickinson in widely different ways created poetic
forms that are an extension of content. Between them they helped modern poetry
find its most compelling subject in its embrace of the common, in grasping the
immediacies of our lives with a visionary intensity so that facts flower into
truths, in Thoreaus phrase. Transcendentalism also remains a shaping force
at the heart of American philosophy, but unlike its role in literature, its
centrality to American philosophy has only recently been argued, by contemporary
philosophers such as Stanley Cavell and Cornel West. To trace this lineage more
precisely, we can return to Nature, which begins with a distinction between
the ME and the NOT ME. Any reader of German philosophy would then predict that
through a long series of dialectical manipulations of abstract propositions
the two turn out to be identical, two faces of the same unitary reality. But
Emerson takes a different road and immediately collapses the distinction through
a direct personal experience, that of crossing a bare common and becoming a
transparent eye-ball instead of simply an I. Later in the
work Emerson pulls back from monistic Idealism not because it is false but because
it disparages nature and leaves no Other to love. Both this privileging of direct
experience over coherent system-building and this weighing of philosophical
propositions not by their truth value but by how best they help us live were
to be developed later in the century by William James and John Dewey in Americas
most crucial contribution to philosophy, Pragmatism. Both Transcendentalism
and Pragmatism articulate and conceptualize peculiarly American dispositions
towards knowing, as Daniel Boorstin writes: We sometimes forget how gradual
was the discovery of America; it was a by-product of the occupation
of the continent. To act, to move on, to explore also meant to push back the
frontiers of knowledge; this inevitably gave a practical and dynamic character
to the very idea of knowledge. To learn and to act became one. This vision
is at the center of Emersons 1838 address, The American Scholar,
which reunifies divisions that have plagued western philosophy such as contemplation
vs. action, soul vs. body, concept vs. specific object. The Transcendentalists
and Pragmatists viewed knowledge and cultural forms not as perpetual truths
but as temporary constructions, and insisted that all such constructions be
open to the tests of continuing experience, that we put more faith in the minds
ability to order the world moment by moment than in complete and self-enclosed
systems.
For this reason Transcendentalism remains in American life less as a specific
doctrine-no one now calls oneself a Transcendentalist-than as presiding
spirit behind many movements that resisting the dominant culture. The writings
of Thoreau, for example, shaped both the passive resistance methods of the civil
rights movement and the underlying vision of the ecology movement. Margaret
Fuller and Elizabeth Peabody are role models for feminist intellectuals who
also espouse activism. The Transcendentalist efforts in education were reincarnated
both in Dewey laboratory school and the open school movement of the 1970s,
and Brook Farm was the prototype of many of the communes of this same period.
At its core, Transcendentalism was a youth movement, making eloquently obvious
one of the first generation gaps in American history. Emerson wrote, This
deliquium, this ossification of the soul, is the Fall of Man. The redemption
is lodged in the heart of youth, and went on to contrast the Party of
Hope with the Party of Memory. Based on the foundational American assumption
that the future can be better than the past through imagination and effort,
the Transcendentalists envisioned a culture that would foster further acts of
culture-making, a community that would also liberate the individual, a way of
thinking that would also become a way of doing.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
Albanese, Catherine L. Corresponding Motion: Transcendental Religion and the
New America. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1977.
Barbour, Brian M. American Transcendentalism: An Anthology of Criticism. Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973.
Boller, Paul F. American Transcendentalism, 1830-60: An Intellectual Inquiry.
New York: Putnams, 1974.
Buell, Lawrence. Literary Transcendentalism: Style and Vision in the American
Renaissance. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973.
---. The Transcendentalists in Columbia Literary History of the
United States. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988.
Cavell, Stanley. In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism and Romanticism.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
Francis, Richard. Transcendental Utopias: Individual and Community at Brook
Farm, Fruitlands, and Walden. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1997.
Goodman, Russell B. American Philosophy and the Romantic Tradition. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Gura, Philip F. and Joel Myerson, Critical Essays on American Transcendentalism.
Boston: G. K. Hall, 1982.
Hutchison, William R. The Transcendentalist Ministers: Church Reform in The
New England Renaissance. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959.
Kern, Alexander, The Rise of Transcendentalism, 1815-1860. In Transitions
in American Literary History, ed. Harry Hayden Clark. Durham: Duke University
Press, 1954. 245-314.
Levin, Jonathan. The Poetics of Transition: Emerson, Pragmatism, and American
Literary Modernism. Durham: Duke University Press, 1999.
Matthiessen, F. O. American Renaissance: Art and Expression in the Age of Emerson.
New York and London: Oxford University Press, 1941.
Miller, Perry. The Transcendentalists: An Anthology. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1950.
Mott, Wesley T. ed. Biographical Dictionary of Transcendentalism. Westport,
CT: Greenwood Press, 1996.
---, ed. Encyclopedia of Transcendentalism. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1996.
Myerson, Joel, ed. The Transcendentalists: A Review of Research and Criticism.
New York: Modern Language Association, 1984.
Barbara Packer, The Transcendentalists, in The Cambridge History
of American Literature: Volume Two, Prose Writing 1820-60, ed. Sacvan Bercovitch.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1995. 329-604.
Poirier, Richard. The Renewal of Literature: Emersonian Reflections. New York:
Random House, 1987.
Rose, Anne C. Transcendentalism as a Social Movement, 1830-1850. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1981.
Simon, Myron, and Thornton H. Parsons, eds. Transcendentalism and its Legacy.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan P, 1966.
Versluis, Arthur. American Transcendentalism and Asian Religions. New York,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
West, Cornel. The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism.
Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989.